Provocative philosopher who argued that
current morality has been cut off from its roots ‘largely thanks to the
Enlightenment’
Catholic Instead of What by Alasdair
MacIntyre with Response by Sean Kelsey
Professor Alasdair MacIntyre's presentation from the Notre Dame Center
for Ethics and Culture's 13th annual Fall Conference (2012): "The
Crowning Glory of the Virtues: Exploring the Many Facets of Justice."
Response by ND professor of philosophy Sean Kelsey.
In 1981, the philosopher Alasdair MacIntyre, who has died aged 96, tore
up the work he was then writing on ethics, and produced what became his
best known book, After Virtue. In it, he excoriated current moral
philosophy and, indeed, current morality itself, complaining that
morality has been cut off from its roots in tradition, and, “largely
thanks to the Enlightenment project”, has ceased to be coherent.
No longer anchored in the Aristotelian notion that humans have a goal
and function, or offering an account of how these are to be fulfilled,
it divorces values from facts. Although calling a person, practice or
action “good” or “bad” seemingly appeals to “an objective and impersonal
standard”, said MacIntyre, there is none available. As he had already
lamented in Against the Self-Images of the Age (1971), Christianity,
Marxism and psychoanalysis have failed to provide an adequate communal
ideology.
Describing himself as “a revolutionary Aristotelian”, he was also an
enthusiast for the ethics of Aristotle’s medieval follower, Thomas
Aquinas. “Forward to the 13th century,” was the motto jokingly
attributed to him.
But by reviving the sort of ethics that identifies “the good” with human
flourishing, MacIntyre aimed to lead us out of “the new dark ages”,
presumably into a better future. He influenced the resurgence of virtue
ethics and communitarianism (he denied espousing either), and the now
fashionable distrust of liberalism, individualism and the Enlightenment.
Remarkable for the number of conflicting beliefs that he could, often
simultaneously, embrace, he was both Protestant and Marxist in the
1960s, then rejected both creeds, and, in the 80s, became a Catholic;
but he always retained his Marxist disgust at capitalism and at the
alienation of modernity.
MacIntyre was 52 when he wrote After Virtue. In A Short History of
Ethics (1966), he had already berated contemporary analytic philosophy
for examining and interpreting moral concepts “apart from their
history”, and portrayed how “moral concepts change as social life
changes” – from the Homeric era when to be agathos (the ideal for
well-born men) was to be kingly, courageous and clever; through
Aristotelian and Christian virtues, which also attuned ethics to an
(albeit different) notion of essential human nature; through the
Enlightenment’s uprooting insistence on autonomous reason; to
20th-century emotivism, which makes ethics merely an expression of
personal preference.
In the late 70s, MacIntyre read the physicist Thomas Kuhn, who regarded
scientific change as a series of “paradigm shifts” rather than a line of
progress, and this gave him, if not a Damascene conversion, then a
clinching certainty as to what was so grotesque about 20th-century
morality: rather than being settled in a particular ethical paradigm, we
operate simultaneously or alternately with several incommensurable moral
traditions. “Imagine,” runs the opening of After Virtue, “that the
natural sciences were to suffer the effects of a catastrophe”, that
science and science teaching have been deliberately abolished, and only
charred pages, disconnected scientific terms and meaningless
incantations remain.
This, said MacIntyre, is our current moral situation. Like the
18th-century Polynesians who talked of “taboos” to Captain Cook but were
unable to say what they meant by that term, all we have are “the
fragments of a conceptual scheme, parts which now lack those contexts
from which their significance is derived”. This is why we regard moral
argument as “necessarily interminable”; we do not even expect to reach
consensus. Should we prioritise human rights and/or the general
happiness, individual choice and/or the general will, hedonism and
will-to-power and/or compassion and self-abnegation?
Aristotle’s ethics in the 4th century BC had assumed that humans have a
telos (function) as rational animals, said MacIntyre. Theistic beliefs –
Jewish, Christian and Muslim – complicated, without essentially
altering, the three-fold ethical scheme: designed to move us from
“human-nature-as-it-happens-to be” via moral education and moral
principles to “human-nature-as-it-could-be-if-it-realised-its-telos”.
Eighteenth-century Enlightenment philosophers, however, in aiming to
liberate us from superstition and authority, and to find a purely
rational basis for ethics, had stripped the self of social identity and
values of any claim to factual status.
Thus morality became a set of inordinate commands and, ultimately, mere
“private arbitrariness”. The unembedded self – essentially “nothing” –
is now obliged to choose its own values.
Admittedly, Jeremy Bentham’s utilitarianism aimed to ground ethics in
the “natural” desire to avoid suffering and maximise pleasure. But
“human happiness is not a unitary simple notion”, said MacIntyre, and
John Stuart Mill’s distinction between higher and lower pleasures only
highlighted utilitarianism’s failure to “provide us with a criterion for
making our key choices”.
MacIntyre was advocating a revised Aristotelianism in which morality is,
once again, not a set of abstract, autonomously selected principles but
a social narrative into which our own personal narrative fits. Bernard
Williams, however, called After Virtue “a brilliant nostalgic fantasy”,
arguing that the socially distinct moral self, rather than being a
product of the Enlightenment, was already present in Plato and
Christianity.
MacIntyre’s subsequent books constituted, it was said, An Interminably
Long History of Ethics, and he himself quoted this with rueful
amusement. Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (1988) and Three Rival
Versions of Moral Enquiry (1990) reiterated that analytic philosophers
purport to present “the timeless form of practical reasoning”, while
actually just “representing the form of practical reason specific to
their own liberal individualist culture”.
It is impossible, argued MacIntyre, to adopt a moral position except
from within a particular tradition. This, since he offers no way of
arbitrating between them, would seem to oblige him to say that any
tradition would be as good as any other, and he has been accused of
being a moral relativist.
However, he said that competing traditions share some standards, so that
anyone is able to apprehend problems in their own tradition and adopt
rationally superior solutions from another, as Aquinas did in
integrating Aristotelianism into Augustine’s theology, ultimately
becoming a better Aristotelian than Aristotle himself. MacIntyre
converted to Thomism and Catholicism, attending mass virtually every
day, but refraining from taking communion on account of having been
divorced.
Having refused to accept a concept of human nature independent of
history, and of particular practices and traditions, MacIntyre
ultimately extended his metaphysical grounding to include, in Dependent
Rational Animals (1999), a biological one. He pointed out how the ethics
of Aristotle, and later of Adam Smith, David Hume and other
Enlightenment philosophers, failed to acknowledge the inevitability of
suffering and dependence in human life.
Their notion of the human was, at least implicitly, a healthy male; they
effectively overlooked women, enslaved people, peasants and
non-Europeans. MacIntyre advocated a more inclusive idea of what it is
to be human, and an acknowledgment of “our resemblances to and
commonality with members of some other intelligent animal species”;
dolphins, he insisted, being closely akin.
Neither the modern nation-state nor the modern family, he argued, can
provide the right sort of political and social association. What would?
MacIntyre sometimes alluded to the cohesive aims of tiny fishing
communities and gestured at the desirability of many small utopias. He
undertook a three-year research project at London Metropolitan
University into whether and in what ways Aquinas’s “conception of the
common good of political societies might find application in the
politics of modern societies” – the result of which was his last book,
Ethics in the Conflicts of Modernity (2016).
Born in Glasgow, Alasdair was the son of Eneas MacIntyre and his wife,
Margaret (nee Chalmers), both Scottish doctors of Irish descent.
Although brought up in London and educated at Epsom college, Surrey, he
was proud of his grounding in the Irish-Scottish Gaelic oral tradition.
While he was studying classics at Queen Mary College, University of
London (1945-49), the surrounding poverty of the East End led him to
become a fervent Marxist.
His first book, Marxism: An Interpretation (1953), demanded a Marxist
renewal of Christianity. Republished in a revised edition as Marxism and
Christianity, it was sympathetic and sceptical about both. Even before
the Hungarian uprising of 1956, he had left the Communist party,
subsequently joining the Socialist Labour League, a Trotskyist group led
by the notorious Gerry Healy. He was in frequent debate with the Marxist
historian EP Thompson, who used to stick notes on the windscreen of
MacIntyre’s car urging him to publish his thoughts on socialist
consciousness.
After gaining an MA at Manchester University (1951), where he then
taught the philosophy of religion, MacIntyre lectured in philosophy at
Leeds University (1957-61), was a research fellow at Nuffield College,
Oxford (1961-62), senior fellow at Princeton (1962-63), fellow of
University College, Oxford (1963-66), and professor of sociology at
Essex University (1966-70).
As dean of students there he opposed the student unrest over the summary
expulsion of three students who had shouted down a speaker from Porton
Down (the research site for chemical and biological warfare).
“Ironically, [the university’s] mistake was to be so liberal,” he said;
and declared that it was because the students had “no real practical
injustices to fight against” that they “had to rebel on ideological
grounds like germ warfare and Vietnam which we were powerless to alter”.
His attitude was considered disingenuous by some (after all, the
university need not have invited the Porton Down speaker); to others, it
was part of his characteristically contradictory and fastidiously
tailored integrity. Partly due to these ructions, he moved to the US to
become professor of history of ideas at Brandeis University (1970-72).
He later held professorships at Boston, Vanderbilt and Duke
universities, and finally at the University of Notre Dame, Indiana
(1988-94 and 2000-10, then emeritus).
MacIntyre disdained the class associations of Oxbridge, and loved his
involvement with London Metropolitan, where he held a post from 2010
onwards. Before speaking at a conference there in 2007, he was handed
pamphlets about a students’ strike over a lecturer’s contract, and he
prefaced his paper with an impromptu diatribe in support of trades
unions and workers’ rights. The first to raise his hand after
MacIntyre’s paper was the Socialist Worker party leader Alex Callinicos,
who accused him of not being a proper revolutionary. MacIntyre replied
that he didn’t know how to make a revolution, but it was clear that
Callinicos didn’t either.
He leaves his third wife, Lynn Sumida Joy; his daughter Jean, from his
first marriage, to Ann Peri, their other daughter, Antonia, having died
in 2000; and a son and a daughter from his second marriage, to Susan
Willans.
Alasdair Chalmers MacIntyre, philosopher, born 12 January 1929; died 21
May 2025
Alasdair MacIntyre - Moral Relativisms
Reconsidered
After Virtue
By Alasdair MacIntyre (third edition) (2007) (pdf)
Common Goods, Frequent Evils by Alasdair
MacIntyre
Alasdair MacIntyre, Rev. John A. O’Brien Senior Research Professor of
Philosophy Emeritus at the University of Notre Dame, gives a keynote
address during the conference "The Common Good as Common Project" on
March 26-28, 2017.
This comment system
requires you to be logged in through either a Disqus account
or an account you already have with Google, X, Facebook or
Yahoo. In the event you don't have an account with any of
these companies then you can create an account with Disqus.
All comments are moderated so they won't display until the
moderator has approved your comment.