Since Ferrier's day the German influence has come in like
a flood, and to this influence may largely be attributed the unsatisfactory
state in which the Hamiltonian philosophy was left. Hamilton thought he
could more effectually combat the views of Hume by calling Kant to the aid
of Reid. The German, like the Scottish, philosopher opposed the views of
Locke which Hume had drawn to their logical conclusion with such lamentable
consequences. Instead, however, of falling back, as Reid did, upon common
sense, Kant revived the innate theory in a new form. Instead of innate
ideas, he postulated for the mind an innate structure by means of which it
is compelled to think under certain necessary and universal forms. Reality,
in that case, was not an affair of sense impressions but of thought forms;
but it needs little reflection to see that Kant brings us no nearer Reality
than Hume. According to Hume all we know is sense impressions; according to
Kant, before we can have knowledge sense impressions must be taken up and
poured into the mould of the categories. But at the end of the process we
are still without guarantee that the knowledge so acquired is in touch with
Reality. In a word, Kant, like Hume, ends in phenomenalism. Hamilton clearly
did not recognize the logical germs of Agnosticism which lay hidden in
Kant's theory of knowledge. When he wrote his famous Edinburgh Review
article he was mainly intent upon checking the career of Cousin, who,
beginning as a disciple of Reid, was coquetting with Schelling and his
theory of the Absolute.
Hamilton, as already mentioned, hoped to bring back
religious feeling by means of faith, but in a scientific age when reason was
proceeding from victory to victory, it was a foregone conclusion that a
theory which chained the human mind to phenomena and refused to soar into
transcendental regions would be eagerly accepted. Accordingly leaders of
scientific thought in this country, and in Germany, under the shadow of the
names of Kant and Hamilton, prided themselves on the adoption of Naturalism
with its contempt for all metaphysical speculations. Upon Hamilton's
doctrine of the Relativity of Knowledge, Herbert Spencer erected his system
of philosophy, and Huxley relates that his Agnosticism owed its origin to
Hamilton's essay on the Philosophy of the Unconditioned.
If Scottish philosophy was to remain true to its
traditions, if its conclusions were to harmonize with the fundamental tenets
of theology— namely, belief in man as an intellectual and moral being
capable of reaching the truth in regard to his relations to God and the
world, the Kantian element which Hamilton had introduced must be got rid of.
Among the first direct attacks upon Hamilton was The Philosophy of the
Infinite by a former student of Hamilton, Henry Calderwood, who
afterwards became Professor of Moral Philosophy in Edinburgh University, a
book which even at this time of day will repay perusal by those who are
perplexed by the prevailing Agnosticism. The late Dr. McCosh also proved a
vigorous assailant of the theory of Hamilton, who has nowhere been more
severely handled than in his own country. Professor Pringle Pattison, who
now occupies Hamilton's chair, deals very fully with the inherent weaknesses
of the doctrine of Relativity in his invaluable Scottish Philosophy,
and comes to the conclusion that any attempt to ingraft the Agnostic
relativity of Kant's Critique upon the Natural Realism of the Scottish
philosophy is contrary to the genius of the latter. Professor James Seth,
who succeeded Calder-wood in the chair of Moral Philosophy, also deals with
the subject in his Ethical Principles. Dealing with the Unknown and
the Unknowable of Hamilton and Spencer from the ethical point of view,
Professor Seth says: "Agnosticism if it is true must carry with it the
ultimate disappearance of religion and with religion of all morality higher
than utility. . . . The practical life is connected in a rational being with
the theoretical; we cannot be permanently illogical either in morality or
religion. The postulate of man's spiritual life is the harmony of nature and
spirit, or the spiritual constitution of the universe." The late Professor
Flint proved himself a discerning and penetrating critic of Hamilton, and in
his work on Agnosticism he shows with his accustomed lucidity and depth the
religious significance of the doctrine of the relativity of knowledge.
The importance of Kant in the history of philosophy is
greatly owing to the fact that out of his system developed two opposite
theories, one which might be labelled Agnostic, and the other Absolute. In
Germany an attempt was made to get rid of the phenomenalism of Kant's system
by laying stress on the innate element, the thought forms which by Fichte
and Schel-ling were made the basis of a system of Idealism which owes its
comprehensive originality to the architectonic intellect of Hegel. Hegel's
aim was to get rid of the dualism which resulted from the doctrine of
relativity. Accepting Kant's dictum that knowledge is constituted by
thought, Hegel concluded that if the world is intelligible only to a self,
analysis of the self should yield the law of the world process, the
universal thought process. With Kant, as we saw, knowledge is relative,
because in the act of thought we are establishing relations, and as Hamilton
understood it, the Absolute exists entirely out of relation, it cannot be
known. To this a Hegelian would reply that the Absolute is not the
unrelated, but the sum of all relations, and that in the act of thought we
are in presence not of mere phenomena, but of the all-embracing Reality.
Introduced into Scotland by the late Dr. Hutchison-Stirling, a thinker of
great intellectual virility, whose writings influenced a generation of
Scottish students, Hegelianism soon became popular, and for a time eclipsed
the Scottish School. Through the writings of the two Cairds and the
enthusiastic advocacy of a band of young men, German modes of thinking
gained the ascendency. In this connection special mention should be made of
Mr. R. B. (now Lord) Haldane's profound work The Pathway to Reality.
Of late there are signs of a reaction. The claims of
Hegelianism have been pitched too high, and among Scottish philosophers
there are those, like Mr. A. J. Balfour, who have dealt it damaging blows.
In the region of philosophy Mr. Balfour has proved himself a master. Among
the most abstruse problems he moves with the ease born of capacity. His
early work, In Defence of Philosophic Doubt, showed him in quite a
Humian vein, directing his critical shafts, not at the metaphysicians, but
at the scientists and the assumptions upon which they were erecting their
creed of Naturalism. In his latest book, The Foundations of Belief,
Mr. Balfour directs his pointed arrows against German Idealism as expounded
by its Scottish and English advocates. It is difficult to find the clue to
Mr. Balfour's own system, as he is much more occupied in criticism of other
thinkers than in scientifically formulating his own views. His object seems
to be not so much to come forth as a constructive thinker as to protest
against the arrogance of scientists on the one hand and the conceit of
Hegelians on the other, and to inculcate the duty of humility in presence of
the vast problem of Existence which reason by itself is competent to
discover, but which by itself is incompetent to solve.
In the writings of the venerable Professor Fraser the
reverential caution of the Scottish school is well displayed. He steers
clear between Agnosticism on the one hand, with its creeping helplessness,
and Hegelianism with its soaring audacity on the other. He does not, like
the Agnostics, belittle reason in presence of the higher problems, nor yet
does he imagine that man with his intellectual measuring line can plumb the
Infinite. Scottish philosophers have always laid stress upon faith as well
as reason in their study of the scheme of things. With Kant they agree in
laying emphasis upon the moral side of the problem, and recognize that by
conscience as well as by reason a way of approach is open to the Infinite.
They deny that reason can do nothing, and that it can do everything. They
strike a middle path; they trust to the universal and necessary principles
of reason, as far as they go, and when the path ends they are prepared to
believe that in the result, as in the process, the true and the good will
prevail, in a word that the universe will be found to be rational through
and through. This is the conclusion to which Professor Fraser comes in his
Gifford lectures on Theism. These lectures, together with his works on Locke
and Berkeley, breathe the spirit of the Scottish philosophy in its best
form, as combining the deepest search into the great problems of life and
destiny with the reverential awe, humility, and trust that spring from
religious feeling.
In the writings of Professor Pringle Pattison we find the
best elements of the German school blended with the characteristics of the
Scottish school. He has been able to combat Agnosticism, which has developed
into Materialism, without running, as Hegelianism is so apt to do, into
Pantheism. Professor Pringle Pattison's Idealism is not of this type. In his
view the highest philosophy does not obliterate the distinction between the
divine and the human, and does not destroy man's hope of immortality. The
system of Idealism which he has reached enables him to meet Materialism at
all points, without, as in the case of Hegelianism, committing philosophic
suicide just when victory is within reach. How, then, does the Professor
combat Materialism? He refuses to accept as valid its interpretation of the
Universe in terms of mechanics. The mechanical view, as he puts it, "through
looking ever backward finds an explanation of things in reducing them to
their lowest terms, and presents us, for example, with Matter and Motion as
philosophical ultimates." View the Universe from the mechanical standpoint,
and when we pass the inorganic sphere we are baffled at every step:
Materialism fails hopelessly to account for life and consciousness, and in
despair is driven to give the whole thing up as an insoluble puzzle. In the
practical sphere this means either Pessimism or Stoicism, according to
individual temperament, or, where the religious instinct is too strong to be
suppressed, the cult of Mysticism or the religion of Humanity. Now,
according to Professor Pringle Pattison, we get rid of these intellectual
nightmares by interpreting life teleologically. In other words, we can only
understand the Universe and man, we can only discern their meaning and value
when we study them, not in their lowest, but in their highest
manifestations.
Inasmuch as the latest product of the Universe is
self-conscious spirit we are justified in postulating Spirit, not Matter, at
the outset of the great evolutionary process. The last word of science, like
that of philosophy, as interpreted by Professor Pringle Pattison, is neither
Agnosticism nor Pantheism, but Theism ; and thus room is found for the
sentiment of religion which with him means self-surrender of the human will
to the divine. Without religion man is a unit struggling with an evil nature
and adverse circumstances; with religion man feels that God is with him.
Religion, in the view of Professor Pringle Pattison, like philosophy, seeks
after the Supreme harmony.
What of human destiny ? Our philosopher will have nothing
to do with systems which mock humanity's highest aspirations, or meet them
with an Agnostic note of interrogation. He can find no consolation in the
progress of humanity if the individual withers and drops into nothingness
like the dead leaves of autumn. In his Man's Place on the Cosmos he
pins his faith to "the old idea of the world as the training-ground of
individual character," and rests firmly in the belief "that whatever of
wisdom and goodness there is in us was not born out of nothing, but has its
fount somewhere and somehow in a more perfect goodness and truth." Professor
Pringle Pattison, it will be seen, links philosophy to religion.
In these days of cosmopolitanism it will not be possible
for any country to claim for itself a distinctively national school of
philosophy. Thought is becoming universalized: into one mighty stream
are flowing innumerable rills. One thing is certain. If the philosophy of
the future is to be victorious in its combat with a materialistic
civilization, with all its soul-deadening and intellect-blighting
influences, it can only be by keeping steadily before the eyes of mankind
the three great problems which throughout its history has ever occupied the
attention of the Scottish School of Philosophy— God, the world, and man.