IT cannot be seriously contended that our methods of
dealing with offenders make for their reform. It may be that some of
those who do not return to prison have been checked in their career
by the treatment they have received, but as a matter of fact, there
are a great many people sent to prison who ought never to have been
there at all. In my opinion it is beyond dispute that our methods
result in the making of criminals; that in the majority of cases
imprisonment not only does no good, but does positive and serious
harm. It should not be forgotten, however, that there is no ground
for supposing that the prison system is intended to reform those who
come within its operation. It keeps them off the street for a time
and prevents them from annoying those who are at liberty; but this
cannot be done without financial cost to the community, and it is
only done at a very serious loss in other respects. The same amount
of money spent in helping them to do well as it costs to imprison
them for doing ill, would prevent many of them from offending; but
before this could be done more would require to be known regarding
the individuals than the mere fact that they have offended against
one or other of our laws.
It is necessary not only to find out where and how
the criminal has gone wrong, but also where and why we have gone
wrong in our method of treating him. Profitable as it would be, no
serious attempt has been made to do this. The most that is done is
to admit the inefficacy of prison treatment and to devise some
theoretical improvement on it. It seems easier for some people to
reason in vacuo—in their own heads— than to examine the facts and
face the consequences. Of late years the public has permitted one
institution after another to be foisted on it at the bidding of
people who have not shown even the most elementary knowledge of the
subject with which they were dealing, and of faddists who want to
regulate other men’s lives by their own. Their opinion of the
offender may be interesting and it may have a value different from
what they place upon it; but it is not nearly as interesting, as
helpful, or as valuable as the offender’s own opinion of the cause
of his fall and of his needs.
The imprisonment and reimprisonment of the habitual
offender had become a scandal. It was recognised that inebriety made
men and women a danger and a nuisance to the family and their
neighbours, but no greater a nuisance than the system by which we
dealt with them. Everybody agreed that imprisonment made them no
better. It made them abstainers only for the time they were in
custody, but it did nothing to destroy the desire for drink. So an
Act of Parliament was passed to enable them to be placed in an
institution of another sort. If the prison failed to reform them,
the Inebriate Homes have proved a more costly, a more ghastly
failure. Instead of finding out the cause of the failure, a
departmental committee, after examining anybody but those who had
been in the homes, has recommended that further parliamentary powers
should be granted to the committees managing them and courts sending
inmates to them. The rational method of procedure would have been
for intelligent and impartial persons to examine those cases which
had been improved, and to estimate how far the improvement was due
to the treatment received. This would not have been a difficult
task, for the cases were few; and having accomplished it, it would
have been equally profitable to examine the many cases of failure
and to seek the causes of that failure. It is much easier, however,
to collect the opinions of officials, of philanthropists, of those
who are interested in prescribing for the conduct of others— in
short, of people who are called authorities on a given subject,
because nobody has been bold enough to challenge them—than to obtain
the confidence and open the mouths of those whose wrongdoing it is
sought to correct. It is a grotesque statement that the Inebriate
Home failed because the wrong people were sent to it; also it is not
true. It would be nearer the mark to say that the home failed
because it was not suited for the treatment of inebriates. For after
all, the very people for whom it was designed to afford treatment
were among those sent there.
The patients chosen for treatment in the Inebriate
Home were carefully selected by a physician experienced in the
treatment of mental diseases. Some of them were mentally affected as
a consequence of their drunkenness, and there is room for supposing
that some took to chink partly on account of a mental defect; but
inebriety is not a physical disease, it is not a mental disease,
although it may have some relationship to physical and mental
diseases. It was because of its being a social disorder that the
State undertook to consider these persons. This being so, each case
could only be rationally considered in relation to the social
condition of the inebriate. Information about the state of their
various internal organs might be useful, but it could never replace
in importance or interest information as to their social condition.
The treatment failed because it was not adapted to
the persons to be treated, but was adapted to the state of mind of
those who, on the strength either of an academic qualification, or a
belief in their fitness to judge people who are of a lower social
condition, had prescribed a method without any real knowledge of the
persons to whom they sought to apply it. The public pays too much
attention to the utterances of those in authority, and it is
difficult to avoid the habit of mistaking for knowledge what is only
a different kind of ignorance from our own. A thing is not true
because somebody says it; it may be true in spite of that; but it
would repay the trouble were official utterances more closely
scrutinised than they are. Zeal, honesty, integrity, may be present
in the official, and he may be a very talented man as well, and yet
he may lead matters into a sad mess. The less he is questioned, the
more he is suffered to go on unchecked, the worse for him and for
those whose servant he is. The good servant may become a very bad
master. Then all official persons are not equally able. If a man has
not wit, it is not likely to be developed in him by giving him a
title or a uniform. If he has not much wisdom, he is not likely to
become less foolish even though you place him in the seat of
Solomon. The fact that a man holds a position is not proof of his
fitness to fill it; and respect for an office makes it all the more
incumbent on honest men to scrutinise and criticise the actions of
the person who occupies it. Loyalty to the public service is too
often confused with servility to those in the upper ranks, resulting
in something very like a conspiracy to magnify their importance
(which would be a small matter), and to induce the public to attach
an undue weight to what they say, though their statements may appear
foolish enough. All this is quite heterodox doctrine, and in
practice will not tend to make a man’s path smooth; but the orthodox
method of assuming that the higher in authority a person is, the
abler and wiser he must be, has not resulted so satisfactorily that
it should escape challenge.
The official reports of Girgenti Inebriate Home were
a great deal more satisfactory than the results, and the home might
have been in existence yet if the representatives of the public had
not informed themselves of the real state of affairs. A few cures
are put to its credit at a calamitous expense. The cost of keeping a
woman there amounted to between twenty-five and thirty shillings per
week, and the odds were proved to be against her being reformed
after three years’ treatment. In other words, the public were
guaranteed that all persons sent to the home could be kept sober at
a cost of from sixty-five to eighty pounds each per year, but they
had no reason to believe that when this payment ceased on their part
the patient would take her place in the community and remain a sober
citizen. If she was not made better, did she become worse as a
result of her treatment there? In some respects she did. You cannot
meddle with the lives of others without result, for it is impossible
to leave them as you find them.
I remember being visited one morning by a woman who
had left the home after a three years stay there. She had been
drinking before she called on me, and she had some complaints to
make regarding her treatment there. The complaints were trifling in
character, and were more in the nature of gossip than anything else.
I told her that she had cost the community some £200 to keep her
during the last three years, and they seemed to have made a bad
bargain. I advised her to think a little less of her grievances and
a little more of the comfort of her neighbours, and dismissed her
with the usual censure and advice; but she had a case against the
State, although she was not able to express it clearly. I would put
it for her thus: “When you interfered with my life I had fallen into
the habit of drinking, but in the main I earned my own living and
meddled very little with others to their annoyance. I had my
friends, whom your judgment might not approve, but between them and
myself there were common ties. We sympathised with each other and
helped each other. You undertook to reform my life, to break me of
my bad habits, to make me more fit to earn my living without
offending against your laws. You have ruled and governed me for
three years. You put me in a home where my life was regulated for
me; you gave me as companions people with whom I had never
associated before; you compelled me to live in their company; you
taught me nothing that I find of any use to me outside; you kept me
from drinking. It may have been a poor pleasure, but it was the only
one I had. You did not take the taste for it away, and you have
given me nothing to replace it; and now I am three years older, and
you turn me loose on the streets of the city to which I belong, and
in which I am now through your action very much a stranger, and
invite me to work for my living in competition with others. I could
work and did work before you meddled with me; I could work yet, but
I must have something to fill my life as well as work, and I have
taken to drink again, because it is the only thing I know that meets
the need I feel. I am worse off than I was before you started to
reform me. Then I had friends, now I am alone ; for they have gone
their own way: some to death, all of them from me. There is nobody
from whom I can have the sympathy and the help I once had. My
friends had their faults and they knew mine; that was why we were
friends. All you can offer me is patronage, advice, direction from
people whom I don’t know and who don’t know me. The one thing that I
want, which is fellowship, I have not got. You have taught me to
depend on others. You have made me obey your rules, and now you set
me free to make rules for myself, and leave me to drift back into
the place where I was ; to face the same difficulties, the same
temptations, without the companionship of those who had grown into
my life. You have taken three years from my life and you have given
me nothing for it. Give me back my life or justify your interference
with it by fitting me to become a better citizen than I was.” This
is something like what the woman appeared to feel and tried to say,
and there is really no answer to it. It is not a wise proceeding to
treat the lives of men and women as toys with which we can play, and
throw them aside without practical regard for consequences when we
are tired of the game. If we do not direct them, they will direct
themselves, and the less fitted they are to do so the worse for us.
I remember one woman who was an inmate of a home, but who had been
employed on a farm outside under licence. Her behaviour was
excellent; she was a good worker, although she had had over a
hundred convictions for drunkenness before her admission to the
home. She always had been a good worker in the intervals between the
drinks. She conformed to the terms of the licence, whatever these
were, and seemed to be a reformed character. I suggested to her that
it was perfectly clear that, though she could not resist the
temptations incident to life in the slums of a great city, she might
continue for an indefinite period to live a useful life in the
country. She replied, “As soon as my three years are up I am going
back to the town,” and she kept her promise, with the result that
she went back to her drinking. In her case it was proved that she
could behave for a long period when the only alternative presented
to a regulated life outside an institution was a more rigidly
regulated life inside an institution. She preferred the outside farm
to the home, but she preferred the streets of the city to either,
and her case raises the question whether it is advisable to withdraw
all control from those like her. She did not require to be
continually overlooked by officials in order that she should conform
to the law. Her life was left under the inspection of the
inhabitants of the district in which she worked, and it is quite
conceivable that she might have been working there yet, if she had
not known that the reward of restraining herself would be not so
much a change in character, as freedom from any supervision when a
fixed term had expired.
The cause of the failure of the Inebriate Home did
not lie in the character of the inmates or of the officials who were
placed over them, but in the defect inherent in all institutions;
the fact that the manner of living in them differs essentially from
anything that obtains outside. They are all founded more or less on
the military model, and the military model and the industrial model
are different. Far more than most of us suspect we are the creatures
of habit:—often of habit acquired slowly, gradually, and
unconsciously. To remove ourselves from one place to another implies
the breaking off from some habits, but it also implies the formation
of others. It did not need the experience of the Inebriate Home to
let us know that men might be removed from the opportunity of
drinking for long periods and, on return to their former conditions,
resume the habit. Years of imprisonment, where teetotalism is
rigidly enforced and where the diet is of a non-stimulating
character, did not make the men who were submitted to it abstain
from drinking on their release. The objectionable habit can only be
cured through being replaced by something which is of equal
interest, has greater power, and enables the man to live his life
without being a nuisance to his neighbours.
When men or women are placed in association with one
another, they have to find some common bond of interest. In every
voluntary association this is recognised. Religion causes some to
cut themselves off from the world and to devote their lives to its
pursuit. Men differing in social positions, in age, in experience,
in character, in temperament, join together to form a community. The
one thing they have in common is their form of belief. They may
differ as widely as possible in their views on other subjects, but
these differences are not the thing that holds them together. They
would rather tend of themselves to break up the association, since
disagreement drives people apart. The differences are only tolerable
because of the bond of agreement which is strong enough to
compensate them. On this subject and around it they may talk. The
experience of each will interest the other, will enlighten him, will
at any rate be considered by him. The same is true of political
associations. Differences there are amongst the members, but these
differences cannot go beyond the point at which some common
agreement balances them, without breaking up the association.
Inebriate Homes and other reformatory institutions
are not voluntary associations, but there can be no intercourse
amongst their inmates that is not based on some experience common to
them all. In the Inebriate Homes the common factor is inebriety.
However much the inmates may differ in other respects, in this they
are all alike : that they have indulged in drink to such an extent
that the law has interfered to deal with them, and so the question
that every newcomer has to face is, “Why are you here?” They are
compelled to associate with one another, and they will get on the
better together for each knowing something of the others’ story.
Scenes are recalled that had better be forgotten. Time spent in
regretting the past while detailing its incident may result, and
often does, in a repetition of the evils which are deplored.
Better that the mind should dwell on something else
than on the errors of time past. It is a common thing to see a man
begin to tell a wild episode or experience of his earlier years, and
to observe that beneath his expressions of criticism and regret
there is a certain tone of satisfaction that he has been through it,
and a lingering reminiscence of the enjoyment he has had in it. He
condemns the folly, admits it was a mistake, and shows quite clearly
that it was quite a pleasure at the time. Talking over the past
brings it back and keeps the memory of it alive, and persistence in
this course may cause that which has been regarded with disgust to
become a thing that is desired, even a thing that is longed for. I
remember a conversation with an inmate on the occasion of a visit I
made to an Inebriate Home. I had known her as a habitual offender
for years before her reformation was undertaken, and at this time
she had been in the institution for more than a year. I
congratulated her on the improvement in her appearance, and at the
end of our talk she said, “It’s a’ quite true, I am better housed
than I ever was. Ma meat is a’ that a body could want, and I get it
mair easily than I did ootside. The work’s no o’er-hard, and the
officials are kind. There are bits o’ rows, of course, noo and then;
whaur there are so many weemen you couldna expect onything else; but
there’s naething to complain of. The country’s real bonny in the
summer, but I get tired of the country. I am a toon bird like
yoursel’, doctor, and I weary for the streets.” I suggested to her
that since she was so well off and could be suited on the expiry of
her term with a place where she would not have the same inducements
to drink as she had had, she should make up her mind to keep away
from the town; but she answered, “No; it’s a’ very nice and
comfortable, but I wouldna gie a walk doon the Candleriggs for the
haill o’ it.” Of course she ultimately had a walk down the
Candleriggs, followed by a drive to prison; but it was quite
apparent that this longing for her old haunts was the result of her
failure to be impressed by interests that were equally absorbing,
and that would become more powerful. Had such an interest developed
in her, the Candleriggs would have been merely an empty sentiment.
It would have occupied the position that “Bonnie Scotland” has in
the minds of so many of the Scots who, having taken up their
residence abroad, and having become absorbed in their affairs, stay
there—afraid to return lest they lose even the sentiment. Just as in
the religious community the members are stimulated to welldoing, in
the reformatory the association of people whose common bond is their
offence stimulates them to wrongdoing, or at least tends to hinder
them from breaking off their old interests.
Institutional life has points of difference from life
outside, which cause the formation of habits that are detrimental to
the inmates when they return to the community. They are lodged
usually on the model of the barracks; though this does not apply to
the lodging of prisoners in prison, as they have separate rooms.
Outside an institution most people do not sleep in dormitories or
live in common rooms. They may live and sleep in the same room, but
the only lodging outside which is on the same model as the dormitory
is the common lodging-house, and that is the last place to which
anyone would desire that a reformed offender should go.
In an institution division of labour is carried out
for reasons of economy. The superintendent directs that different
sets of people should perform different duties. Even if all the
persons are changed at intervals from one set of duties to another,
with a view to each inmate learning to do all parts of the work
which is necessary in order that the place may be kept in proper
condition, the habit formed is different from that of the housewife
outside, who daily has to go over the whole round of her work. She
is not responsible for doing a part, knowing that some other is
responsible for some other part. Not only each part of the work
engages her attention in its turn, but she is accountable for the
whole ; whether she does it well or ill is beside the point, which
is, that there is nobody to rule her and no one whom she can hold
accountable for her neglect. The habits of housekeeping acquired by
the inmates of a home may tend to make them good servants, but they
are certainly not the kind likely to make them more fit than they
were to undertake the management of a house of their own; for they
do not manage, they are managed. |